The Unraveling of Scientific Materialism
Phillip E. Johnson
In
a retrospective essay on Carl Sagan in the January 9, 1997 New York Review
of Books,
Harvard Genetics Professor Richard Lewontin tells how he first met Sagan at a
public debate in Arkansas in 1964. The two young scientists had been coaxed by
senior colleagues to go to Little Rock to debate the affirmative side of the question:
"RESOLVED, that the theory of evolution is as proved as is the fact that
the earth goes around the sun." Their main opponent was a biology
professor from a fundamentalist college, with a Ph.D. from the University of
Texas in Zoology. Lewontin reports no details from the debate, except to say
that "despite our absolutely compelling arguments, the audience
unaccountably voted for the opposition."
Of
course, Lewontin and Sagan attributed the vote to the audience's prejudice in
favor of creationism. The resolution was framed in such a way, however, that
the affirmative side should have lost even if the jury had been composed of Ivy
League philosophy professors. How could the theory of evolution even
conceivably be "proved" to the same degree as "the fact that the
earth goes around the sun"? The latter is an observable feature of
present-day reality, whereas the former deals primarily with non-repeatable
events of the very distant past. The appropriate comparison would be between
the theory of evolution and the accepted theory of the origin of the solar
system.
If
"evolution" referred only to currently observable phenomena like
domestic animal breeding or finch-beak variation, then winning the debate
should have been no problem for Lewontin and Sagan even with a fundamentalist
jury. The statement "We breed a great variety of dogs," which rests
on direct observation, is much easier to prove than the statement that the
earth goes around the sun, which requires sophisticated reasoning. Not even the
strictest biblical literalists deny the bred varieties of dogs, the variation
of finch beaks, and similar instances within types. The more controversial
claims of large-scale evolution are what arouse skepticism. Scientists may
think they have good reasons for believing that living organisms evolved
naturally from nonliving chemicals, or that complex organs evolved by the
accumulation of micromutations through natural selection, but having reasons is
not the same as having proof. I have seen people, previously inclined to
believe whatever "science says," become skeptical when they realize
that the scientists actually do seem to think that variations in finch beaks or
peppered moths, or the mere existence of fossils, proves all the vast claims of
"evolution." It is as though the scientists, so confident in their
answers, simply do not understand the question.
Carl
Sagan described the theory of evolution in his final book as the doctrine that
"human beings (and all the other species) have slowly evolved by natural
processes from a succession of more ancient beings with no divine intervention
needed along the way." It is the alleged absence of divine intervention
throughout the history of life--the strict materialism of the orthodox theory--that
explains why a great many people, only some of whom are biblical
fundamentalists, think that Darwinian evolution (beyond the micro level) is
basically materialistic philosophy disguised as scientific fact. Sagan himself
worried about opinion polls showing that only about 10 percent of Americans
believe in a strictly materialistic evolutionary process, and, as Lewontin's
anecdote concedes, some of the doubters have advanced degrees in the relevant
sciences. Dissent as widespread as that must rest on something less easily
remedied than mere ignorance of facts.
Lewontin
eventually parted company with Sagan over how to explain why the theory of
evolution seems so obviously true to mainstream scientists and so doubtful to
much of the public. Sagan attributed the persistence of unbelief to ignorance
and hucksterism and set out to cure the problem with popular books, magazine
articles, and television programs promoting the virtues of mainstream science
over its fringe rivals. Lewontin, a Marxist whose philosophical sophistication
exceeds that of Sagan by several orders of magnitude, came to see the issue as
essentially one of basic intellectual commitment rather than factual knowledge.
The
reason for opposition to scientific accounts of our origins, according to
Lewontin, is not that people are ignorant of facts, but that they have not
learned to think from the right starting point. In his words, "The primary
problem is not to provide the public with the knowledge of how far it is to the
nearest star and what genes are made of. . . . Rather, the problem is to get
them to reject irrational and supernatural explanations of the world, the
demons that exist only in their imaginations, and to accept a social and
intellectual apparatus, Science, as the only begetter of truth." What the
public needs to learn is that, like it or not, "We exist as material
beings in a material world, all of whose phenomena are the consequences of
material relations among material entities." In a word, the public needs
to accept materialism, which means that they must put God (whom Lewontin calls
the "Supreme Extraterrestrial") in the trash can of history where
such myths belong.
Although
Lewontin wants the public to accept science as the only source of truth, he
freely admits that mainstream science itself is not free of the hokum that
Sagan so often found in fringe science. As examples he cites three influential
scientists who are particularly successful at writing for the public: E. O.
Wilson, Richard Dawkins, and Lewis Thomas,
each
of whom has put unsubstantiated assertions or counterfactual claims at the very
center of the stories they have retailed in the market. Wilson's Sociobiology and On Human Nature rest on the surface of
a quaking marsh of unsupported claims about the genetic determination of
everything from altruism to xenophobia. Dawkins' vulgarizations of Darwinism
speak of nothing in evolution but an inexorable ascendancy of genes that are
selectively superior, while the entire body of technical advance in
experimental and theoretical evolutionary genetics of the last fifty years has
moved in the direction of emphasizing nonselective forces in evolution. Thomas,
in various essays, propagandized for the success of modern scientific medicine
in eliminating death from disease, while the unchallenged statistical compilations
on mortality show that in Europe and North America infectious diseases . . .
had ceased to be major causes of mortality by the early decades of the
twentieth century.
Lewontin
laments that even scientists frequently cannot judge the reliability of scientific
claims outside their fields of specialty, and have to take the word of
recognized authorities on faith. "Who am I to believe about quantum
physics if not Steven Weinberg, or about the solar system if not Carl Sagan?
What worries me is that they may believe what Dawkins and Wilson tell them
about evolution."
One
major living scientific popularizer whom Lewontin does not trash is his Harvard
colleague and political ally Stephen Jay Gould. Just to fill out the picture,
however, it seems that admirers of Dawkins have as low an opinion of Gould as
Lewontin has of Dawkins or Wilson. According to a 1994 essay in the New York
Review of Books
by John Maynard Smith, the dean of British neo-Darwinists, "the
evolutionary biologists with whom I have discussed his [Gould's] work tend to
see him as a man whose ideas are so confused as to be hardly worth bothering
with, but as one who should not be publicly criticized because he is at least
on our side against the creationists. All this would not matter, were it not
that he is giving non biologists a largely false picture of the state of
evolutionary theory." Lewontin fears that non-biologists will fail to
recognize that Dawkins is peddling pseudoscience; Maynard Smith fears exactly
the same of Gould.
If
eminent experts say that evolution according to Gould is too confused to be
worth bothering about, and others equally eminent say that evolution according
to Dawkins rests on unsubstantiated assertions and counterfactual claims, the
public can hardly be blamed for suspecting that grand-scale evolution may rest
on something less impressive than rock-solid, unimpeachable fact. Lewontin
confirms this suspicion by explaining why "we" (i.e., the kind of
people who read the New York Review) reject out of hand the view of those who
think they see the hand of the Creator in the material world:
We
take the side of science in spite of the patent absurdity of some of its
constructs, in spite of its failure to fulfill many of its extravagant promises of
health and life, in spite of the tolerance of the scientific community for
unsubstantiated just-so stories, because we have a prior commitment, a
commitment to materialism. It is not that the methods and institutions of
science somehow compel us to accept a material explanation of the phenomenal
world, but, on the contrary, that we are forced by our a priori adherence to
material causes to create an apparatus of investigation and a set of concepts
that produce material explanations, no matter how counterintuitive, no matter
how mystifying to the uninitiated. Moreover, that materialism is absolute, for
we cannot allow a Divine Foot in the door. The eminent Kant scholar Lewis Beck
used to say that anyone who could believe in God could believe in anything. To
appeal to an omnipotent deity is to allow that at any moment the regularities
of nature may be ruptured, that miracles may happen.
That
paragraph is the most insightful statement of what is at issue in the
creation/evolution controversy that I have ever read from a senior figure in the
scientific establishment. It explains neatly how the theory of evolution can
seem so certain to scientific insiders, and so shaky to the outsiders. For
scientific materialists the materialism comes first; the science comes
thereafter. We
might more accurately term them "materialists employing science." And
if materialism is true, then some materialistic theory of evolution has to be
true simply as a matter of logical deduction, regardless of the evidence. That
theory will necessarily be at least roughly like neo-Darwinism, in that it will
have to involve some combination of random changes and law-like processes
capable of producing complicated organisms that (in Dawkins' words) "give
the appearance of having been designed for a purpose."
The
prior commitment explains why evolutionary scientists are not disturbed when
they learn that the fossil record does not provide examples of gradual
macroevolutionary transformation, despite decades of determined effort by
paleontologists to confirm neo-Darwinian presuppositions. That is also why
biological chemists like Stanley Miller continue in confidence even when
geochemists tell them that the early earth did not have the oxygen-free
atmosphere essential for producing the chemicals required by the theory of the
origin of life in a prebiotic soup. They reason that there had to be some
source (comets?) capable of providing the needed molecules, because otherwise
life would not have evolved. When evidence showed that the period available on
the early earth for the evolution of life was extremely brief in comparison to
the time previously posited for chemical evolution scenarios, Carl Sagan calmly
concluded that the chemical evolution of life must be easier than we had
supposed, because it happened so rapidly on the early earth.
That
is also why neo-Darwinists like Richard Dawkins are not troubled by the
Cambrian Explosion, where all the invertebrate animal groups appear suddenly
and without identifiable ancestors. Whatever the fossil record may suggest,
those Cambrian animals had to evolve by accepted neo-Darwinian means, which is
to say by material processes requiring no intelligent guidance or supernatural
input. Materialist philosophy demands no less. That is also why Niles Eldredge,
surveying the absence of evidence for macroevolutionary transformations in the
rich marine invertebrate fossil record, can observe that "evolution always
seems to happen somewhere else," and then describe himself on the very
next page as a "knee-jerk neo-Darwinist." Finally, that is why Darwinists
do not take critics of materialist evolution seriously, but speculate instead
about "hidden agendas" and resort immediately to ridicule. In their
minds, to question materialism is to question reality. All these specific
points are illustrations of what it means to say that "we" have an a
priori commitment to materialism.
The
scientific leadership cannot afford to disclose that commitment frankly to the
public. Imagine what chance the affirmative side would have if the question for
public debate were rephrased candidly as "RESOLVED, that everyone should
adopt an a priori commitment to materialism." Everyone would see what many
now sense dimly: that a methodological premise useful for limited purposes has
been expanded to form a metaphysical absolute. Of course people who define
science as the search for materialistic explanations will find it useful to
assume that such explanations always exist. To suppose that a philosophical
preference can validate a cherished scientific theory is to define "science"
as a way of supporting prejudice. Yet that is exactly what the Darwinists seem
to be doing, when their evidence is evaluated by critics who are willing to
question materialism.
One
of those critics, bearing impeccable scientific credentials, is Michael Behe,
who argues that complex molecular systems (such as bacterial and protozoan
flagella, immune systems, blood clotting, and cellular transport) are
"irreducibly complex." This means that the systems incorporate
elements that interact with each other in such complex ways that it is
impossible to describe detailed, testable Darwinian mechanisms for their
evolution. (My review of Behe's Darwin's Black Box appeared in FT,
October 1996.) Never mind for now whether you think that Behe's argument can
prevail over sustained opposition from the materialists. The primary dispute is
not over who is going to win, but about whether the argument can even get
started. If we know a priori that materialism is true, then contrary evidence
properly belongs under the rug, where it has always duly been swept.
For
Lewontin, the public's determined resistance to scientific materialism
constitutes "a deep problem in democratic self-governance." Quoting
Jesus' words from the Gospel of John, he thinks that "the truth that makes
us free" is not an accumulation of knowledge, but a metaphysical
understanding (i.e., materialism) that sets us free from belief in supernatural
entities like God. How is the scientific elite to persuade or bamboozle the
public to accept the crucial starting point? Lewontin turns for guidance to the
most prestigious of all opponents of democracy, Plato. In his dialog the Gorgias, Plato reports a
debate between the rationalist Socrates and three sophists or teachers of
rhetoric. The debaters all agree that the public is incompetent to make
reasoned decisions on justice and public policy. The question in dispute is
whether the effective decision should be made by experts (Socrates) or by the
manipulators of words (the sophists).
In
familiar contemporary terms, the question might be stated as whether a court
should appoint a panel of impartial authorities to decide whether the
defendant's product caused the plaintiff's cancer, or whether the jury should
be swayed by rival trial lawyers each touting their own experts. Much turns on
whether we believe that the authorities are truly impartial, or whether they
have interests of their own. When the National Academy of Sciences appoints a
committee to advise the public on evolution, it consists of persons picked in
part for their scientific outlook, which is to say their a priori acceptance of
materialism. Members of such a panel know a lot of facts in their specific
areas of research and have a lot to lose if the "fact of evolution"
is exposed as a philosophical assumption. Should skeptics accept such persons
as impartial fact-finders? Lewontin himself knows too much about cognitive
elites to say anything so naive, and so in the end he gives up and concludes
that "we" do not know how to get the public to the right starting
point.
Lewontin
is brilliantly insightful, but too crankily honest to be as good a manipulator
as his Harvard colleague Stephen Jay Gould. Gould displays both his talent and
his unscrupulousness in an essay in the March 1997 issue of Natural History, entitled
"Nonoverlapping Magisteria" and subtitled "Science and religion
are not in conflict, for their teachings occupy distinctly different
domains." With a subtitle like that, you can be sure that Gould is out to
reassure the public that evolution leads to no alarming conclusions. True to
form, Gould insists that the only dissenters from evolution are
"Protestant fundamentalists who believe that every word of the Bible must
be literally true." Gould also insists that evolution (he never defines the
word) is "both true and entirely compatible with Christian belief."
Gould is familiar with nonliteralist opposition to evolutionary naturalism, but
he blandly denies that any such phenomenon exists. He even quotes a letter
written to the New York Times in answer to an op-ed essay by Michael Behe,
without revealing the context. You can do things like that when you know that
the media won't call you to account.
The
centerpiece of Gould's essay is an analysis of the complete text of Pope John
Paul's statement of October 22, 1996 to the Pontifical Academy of Sciences
endorsing evolution as "more than a hypothesis." He fails to quote
the Pope's crucial qualification that "theories of evolution which, in
accordance with the philosophies inspiring them, consider the spirit as
emerging from the forces of living matter or as a mere epiphenomenon of this
matter, are incompatible with the truth about man." Of course, a theory
based on materialism assumes by definition that there is no "spirit"
active in this world that is independent of matter. Gould knows this perfectly
well, and he also knows, just as Richard Lewontin does, that the evidence
doesn't support the claims for the creative power of natural selection made by
writers such as Richard Dawkins. That is why the philosophy that really
supports the theory has to be protected from critical scrutiny.
Gould's
essay is a tissue of half-truths aimed at putting the religious people to
sleep, or luring them into a "dialogue" on terms set by the
materialists. Thus Gould graciously allows religion to participate in
discussions of morality or the meaning of life, because science does not claim
authority over such questions of value, and because "Religion is too
important to too many people for any dismissal or denigration of the comfort
still sought by many folks from theology." Gould insists, however, that
all such discussion must cede to science the power to determine the facts, and one of the facts
is an evolutionary process that is every bit as materialistic and purposeless
for Gould as it is for Lewontin or Dawkins. If religion wants to accept a
dialogue on those terms, that's fine with Gould--but don't let those religious
people think they get to make an independent judgment about the evidence that
supposedly supports the "facts." And if the religious people are
gullible enough to accept materialism as one of the facts, they won't be
capable of causing much trouble.
The
debate about creation and evolution is not deadlocked. Propagandists like Gould
try to give the impression that nothing has changed, but essays like Lewontin's
and books like Behe's demonstrate that honest thinkers on both sides are near
agreement on a redefinition of the conflict. Biblical literalism is not the
issue. The issue is whether materialism and rationality are the same thing.
Darwinism is based on an a priori commitment to materialism, not on a
philosophically neutral assessment of the evidence. Separate the philosophy
from the science, and the proud tower collapses. When the public understands
this clearly, Lewontin's Darwinism will start to move out of the science
curriculum and into the department of intellectual history, where it can gather
dust on the shelf next to Lewontin's Marxism.
Phillip
E. Johnson is Professor of Law at the University of California at Berkeley and
author, most recently, of Defeating Darwinism by Opening Minds (InterVarsity Press).
http://www.firstthings.com/ftissues/ft9711/articles/johnson.html
Copyright (c) 1997 First Things 77 (November 1997): 22-25.